Democracy and representation: lessons from Alabama’s blanket abortion ban

Last week, the Senate of the State of Alabama passed the most restrictive abortion law in the United States. It allows abortions only when there is a “serious health risk” to the mother, precluding them in cases of rape, and raising penalties to up to 99 years in prison for doctors who practice them. Leaving the substance of the law aside, I am interested here in the fact that the 25 Senators who voted to pass it are all white men. This gives us a good opportunity to revisit, in terms of democratic legitimacy, the philosophical foundations of electoral policies that promote the participation of women in politics (like female quotas in electoral lists).

Pro-choice protesters in Chicago, Illinois
Protesters in Chicago, Illinois denounce policies restricting women’s reproductive rights. Photo: Flickr Creative Commons.

To begin with, democracy is not a binary term. That is, countries and institutions are not democratic or antidemocratic. Democracy is best understood, according to political philosopher Adam Swift, as varying in degrees along four different morally salient dimensions: (a) directness of decisions, (b) accountability of representatives, (c) equality of influence, and (d) scope of the democratic authority. I believe, however, there is a fifth dimension upon which to analyse democracies: quality of representation. In this sense, how democratically legitimate is a law that directly affects women but is passed only by men?

On the question of representation, political theorist Iris Marion Young explains that there are three modes by which a person can be represented: interest, opinion, and perspective. While representing interests or opinions usually entails promoting outcomes, representing perspectives usually entails promoting starting points of the discussion. Young’s  vision of representation is both more robust and realistic and forces us to think about ways to make a representative democracy more legitimate.

But can’t men represent women’s perspectives? Leaving aside the theoretical question, this has been the argument to deprive women of the most basic democratic participation (the vote) under the excuse that they were represented either by their fathers or their husbands. Needless to say, this has done little for women’s rights. Representation as perspective demands that representatives belong and are voted by the group they represent, since it assures that they share the social experiences of that group (and, among other aspects, reduces the moral hazard of representation).

The second step to analyse policies in terms of democratic legitimacy is whether they promote or hinder any of the justifications of democracy. It is usually said by critics that female  quotas affect the freedom of both the electorate and political parties, and that they violate equality by discriminating against men. Both of these premises are false. From a starting point of structural inequality between men and women, both freedom to choose and equality are formal illusions. How free to choose are Alabama black women (namely the most affected collective by the passing of this law) whose options in the voting booth are “white man A” and “white man B”? How equal are women to men if, because of prejudice and a lack of opportunity, they cannot gain access to elected office (not even to electoral lists)? The entire point of affirmative action is to correct self-perpetuating structural inequalities. What is attacked as a violation of formal freedom and equality is nothing but a material attempt to equalise the playing field, unfairly tilted toward an advantaged group (in this case, men). In other words, an attempt to allow more than half of the population to be able to choose a better quality of representation.

In the same vein, female quotas promote two other instrumental justifications of democracy: its capacity to reach better or correct decisions, and its perceived legitimacy. First, promoting representation of women by women allows a more robust debate and deliberation within the walls of legislatures, since it aims to include women who will bring with them their different backgrounds and perspectives. Second, a democracy that is more representative of its demos has a better probability of generating compliance. Citizens are more likely to comply with legislative decisions and view them as their own if they feel that those who took them did so representing and debating their viewpoints. This is so, since they will have a sense of having participated in the debate themselves.

But why stop there? Why not create dozens of quotas? Intersectionality tells us that the male-female dichotomy essentialises the experiences of millions of women (and men) by forcing them to fit into boxes of heteronormativity. Far from negating this framework of analysis, this critique invites us to deepen the discussion in the same terms. That is, how can we continue to improve the quality of representation? Of course, such a discussion will have to bear in mind other dimensions and justifications of democracy as well as the feasibility and constraints of balkanizing representation.

Finer points of democratic theory aside, however, the democratic credentials of this particular law and of the Alabama Senate, which has the lowest percentage of women in the entire U.S. (11,7%), are seriously in doubt. I do not intend here to propose a specific scheme of electoral engineering (uninominal districts like those in the US pose a much bigger challenge than other systems with proportional representation). What I do intend, however, is to recognise the salience of quality of representation as a morally relevant dimension for analysing the democratic credentials of a decision and a system. This entails the inescapable mandate of enacting electoral policies to try to achieve what common sense already tells us: that legislatures should look more like the people they represent.

Sergio Giuliano is an Argentine lawyer with an LLM from Yale Law School and he is an alumnus of the Blavatnik School of Government (MPP 2017). He specialises in constitutional law and international human rights law. He was legal adviser to the Minority Leader of the Argentine Congress and clerked for the Vice-President of the European Court of Human Rights.

Join the discussion